The Yale Law Journal

VOLUME
121
2011-2012
Forum

When Machines Are Watching: How Warrantless Use of GPS Surveillance Technology Violates the Fourth Amendment Right Against Unreasonable Searches

11 Oct 2011

Unfortunately, in drawing lines between technology such as powerful binoculars that merely enhance the senses of law enforcement officials and technology such as thermal imaging devices that create new superhuman powers, the Justices have offered confusing guidance to lower courts. At times, they have relied on a distinction between sense enhancement and sense creation, a superficial distinction that fails to delineate when new surveillance technology is problematic. At other times, the Court has reverted to language reminiscent of past Fourth Amendment doctrine requiring some sort of physical trespass in order to trigger the warrant requirement. The Court rejected that doctrine in Katz v. United States, when it recognized that new technologies make a private space/public space line unworkable. However, the Justices’ failure to explain clearly the source of their concerns about new technology, coupled with their haphazard use of language, has confused the lower courts and commentators. This confusion has led some to conclude that the use of GPS surveillance technology for prolonged, automated surveillance of targets should not be considered a “search” subject to the Fourth Amendment, at least to the extent that the surveillance occurs on public streets.

As we argue in this Essay, the use of GPS surveillance for prolonged monitoring without a warrant cannot pass muster under the Fourth Amendment. It may seem at first glance that GPS tracking of public actions—actions that the police can otherwise follow without a warrant in the status quo—is harmless from a privacy perspective. After all, if cops can tail a suspect for days or weeks without a warrant, what difference does it make if the tracking is done by an undercover officer or a GPS device under the hood of a suspect’s car? However, when “machines are watching”—that is, when tracking is automated and extended for prolonged periods of time—the potential for abuse grows larger. In such circumstances, the warrant requirement, with its limited exceptions, provides a necessary check on overreach by law enforcement authorities.

This Essay is organized in three Parts. In Part I, we outline the Fourth Amendment’s structural protections against law enforcement abuse and explain the Court’s historic approach to new surveillance technologies. While the Court’s approach is undertheorized, we show that the Court has carefully examined new technologies to prevent technological end-runsaround existing legal doctrine that seeks to protect personal privacy. We maintain that the Court’s doctrinal distinction between sense-enhancing and sense-creating technology is effectively a proxy for the Court’s underlying interest in protecting against governmental abuse. In Part II, we explain why GPS surveillance technology creates unprecedented potential for abuse, and we present anecdotal evidence suggesting that abuse of GPS surveillance technology may be occurring already. Note, though, that our argument does not hinge on the claim that abuse is widespread. Rather, we argue that GPS surveillance poses a real threat, even if (and we have no way of knowing whether this is true) the potential for abuse has not yet been realized except in a limited number of cases. Our conception of the Fourth Amendment differs fundamentally from the Solicitor General’s view, expressed in the government’s brief in Jones, that “[t]he decision whether to apply different constitutional principles to hypothetical programs of mass, suspicionless surveillance can await resolution if such programs ever occur.” We do not believe that the Court must stand aside until “Big Brother” arrives; doing so would render the Fourth Amendment’s protections a “dead letter.”

In Part III, we connect our interpretation of the Fourth Amendment to the “reasonable expectation of privacy” language that looms large in contemporary case law. In our view, a “reasonable expectation of privacy” may be violated even if individuals already anticipate that the information at issue can be accessed by law enforcement officials. Indeed, any other interpretation of that language would yield perverse implications: if “hypothetical programs of mass, suspicionless surveillance” ever arrived, individuals would then have no expectation of privacy once they learned of the surveillance, and the “expectation of privacy” protection—if interpreted literally—would become a nullity.

Our interpretation of the Fourth Amendment is consistent with the concerns underlying past Supreme Court decisions. As Part III explains, control over information about our location is still central to our sense of self. This interpretation of the Fourth Amendment and the individual rights interpretation ultimately converge in GPS cases, and both views counsel in favor of the conclusion that the use of this technology for automated, prolonged surveillance should be subject to the Fourth Amendment’s warrant requirement.

I. The Fourth Amendment and Technological Advances

Most legal commentary on the Fourth Amendment implications of GPS surveillance technology has bypassed the core, structural Fourth Amendment issue. For example, Orin Kerr has distinguished between “public location information obtained from GPS devices” and “private facts” that fall within the ambit of the Fourth Amendment’s protections. In this Essay, we argue that the scholarly focus on the information collected by new technology gives short shrift to the animating and long-honored principle of the Fourth Amendment: protection of the populace from abuse of law enforcement powers. This fundamental principle underlies the Court’s decisions evaluating the application of the Fourth Amendment to the use of new surveillance technologies, including its recent decision requiring a warrant for thermal imaging in Kyllo v. United States. In cases from Katz to Knotts to Kyllo, wherever a new technology carries the potential for police abuse, the Court has allowed its use only as guarded by the warrant requirement, placing a check on the unlimited discretion otherwise afforded officers. As the Supreme Court has acknowledged, “[r]equiring a warrant will have the salutary effect of ensuring that use of [new technology] is not abused.”

Given the Court’s command to examine the reasonableness of an expectation of privacy in determining whether a search has occurred, it is perhaps not surprising that commentators have focused on the nature of the information collected. And we do not mean to say that the nature of the information collected by a technology is irrelevant. If a technology only had the capacity to collect, store, and analyze data in which individuals had no privacy or dignitary interest—such as the information individuals make available to the public in phone books—then neither the abuse of that technology nor the potential for abuse would be of such grave concern. However, as the Court has repeatedly recognized, the means of surveillance, the nature of the technology at issue, and its potential for abuse must be considered as well. Considering these three factors will impact the Court’s analysis of privacy expectations, as we outline in Part III below. We start, however, with an examination of how the Court has treated the potential for law enforcement abuse of surveillance methods in the past.

A. The Fourth Amendment’s Emphasis on Law Enforcement Abuse

As has been thoroughly documented, the Founders designed the Fourth Amendment to protect citizens against arbitrary police invasions, a direct response to unwarranted searches and seizures by British officers targeting political opponents both in England and in the colonies. As the Court cautioned more than eighty years ago, “[t]he Fourth Amendment was adopted in view of long misuse of power in the matter of searches and seizures both in England and the colonies.” The Court sees the Amendment playing a robust role as our primary protection against “a too permeating police surveillance.” And it is the warrant requirement that is the Court’s means of enforcing this protection.

In addition to protecting personal space from invasion, thereby protecting our homes as our castles, the Fourth Amendment also serves a crucial function in preserving an open democratic process and in ensuring the equal treatment of citizens. It stops police from using surveillance to intimidate targeted groups of citizens and prevent their free and equal participation in political organization and discussion. Moreover, the Fourth Amendment’s protections reflect the view that certain individuals are more at risk than others when they gather to discuss politics, transact business, or even seek medical care. To protect against abuse of “discretion,” the Fourth Amendment requires that “the usual inferences which reasonable men draw from evidence . . . be drawn by a neutral and detached magistrate instead of being judged by the officer engaged in the often competitive enterprise of ferreting out crime.” The Court itself has indicated that the warrant requirement and the exclusionary rule are theonly effective limitations on lawless searches and seizures.

B. New Technologies and the Fourth Amendment

When examining the use of new surveillance technologies, the Court has recognized that old Fourth Amendment legal standards may not provide enough protection because a new technology can create powers of surveillance that were not anticipated when old legal standards were developed. The Court therefore discourages the “mechanical” application of doctrinal standards that allow end-runs around Fourth Amendment protections and leave us “at the mercy of advancing technology.” Instead, the Court encourages the adoption of rules that “take account of more sophisticated systems that are already in use or in development.” Any standard applied must meet the broader structural concerns of the Fourth Amendment and “assure[ the] preservation of that degree of privacy against government that existed when the Fourth Amendment was adopted.”

In its decisions examining whether law enforcement use of a new surveillance method should be allowed without the minimal limitations of a warrant, the Court has not hesitated to modify its Fourth Amendment inquiry as necessary to ensure that the purpose underlying the Amendment is carried forward. For example, in Katz, the Court evaluated law enforcement’s use of a novel listening device, one that attached to the outside of phone booths but nevertheless allowed police officers to eavesdrop on a target’s phone conversations. This method met the technical requirements of Fourth Amendment doctrine at the time, which only prohibited physical intrusions into the private sphere. Nevertheless, the Court modified the doctrine to fit new realities, recognizing that the difference between physical and electronic intrusion had “no constitutional significance.” The Court held that the Fourth Amendment protects “people, not places” and emphasized that notions of privacy and improper intrusion cannot be defeated by technological end-runs around previous doctrine.

The Court’s concern about limiting police discretion, police abuse, and the extent to which we become a surveillance state has also been expressed in its cases distinguishing sense-enhancing from sense-creating technologies. Under this line of reasoning, the Court has required a warrant for technologies that do not enhance human senses but operate independently of humans. While the sense enhancement/sense creation doctrine provides some direction to lower courts, reliance on the doctrine is problematic in light of the difficulty in knowing when sense enhancement has crossed the line into sense creation. At other times, the Court has confused the issue by reverting to language reminiscent of the pre-Katz, private space/public space distinction. We submit, however, that none of the cases turn on either of these distinctions. The Court’s decisions are instead animated by the abuse potential of each surveillance technology.

For example, in United States v. Lee, the Court confirmed that no search took place where officers used “searchlights” or “marine glass or field glass” to help them see on the deck of a ship at night. This limited form of sense enhancement did not implicate protections against police abuse any more than what an individual officer watching without binoculars would have done. In contrast, in Walter v. United States, the Court held that using a movie projector—fairly basic technology, even at the time—to view films without a warrant was an unreasonable search under the Fourth Amendment. In Walter, the government argued that agents did not need a warrant to view the films because they were lawfully in possession of the materials. The Court rejected that argument, pointing out the potential for abuse if agents could open sealed letters that were lawfully in the Postal Service’s possession. Underlying the Court’s decision was a desire to provide constitutional protection to unpopular messages.

The Court’s decision in Knotts, which upheld the limited use of beepers without a warrant, purports to rest on the sense enhancement/sense creation distinction. Referencing the searchlights and marine and field glass at issue in Lee, the Court explained that“[n]othing in the Fourth Amendment prohibited the police from augmenting the sensory faculties bestowed upon them at birth with such enhancement as science and technology afforded them in this case.” Yet the language of “sense enhancement” here is mystifying: it is not at all clear what “sense” the beepers “enhanced.” Unlike searchlights or binoculars, the beepers in Knotts did not merely make it easier for the officers to “see.” Indeed, the Court recognized that, but for the beepers, the police would have been unable to ascertain the suspect’s location. It seems therefore that the rationale underlying Knotts was not the sense enhancement/sense creation distinction, but rather the view of the Court that primitive beeper technology was not susceptible to abuse. After all, the Knotts Court specifically reserved the question of technology giving broader surveillance powers and declined to predict the outcome of a case in which technology allowed for “dragnet-type law enforcement.” United States v. Karo, decided one year later, makes clear the limitations of the Knotts decision. The Court held that a warrant was required for monitoring and downloading beeper data when the beeper allowed surveillance of areas that officers would not otherwise have been able to view.

The Court’s most recent discussion of these issues in Kyllo v. United States, which examined the application of the warrant rule to the use of thermal imaging technology, highlights how the Justices consider the abuse potential of a surveillance technology. The Court began by recognizing that it had “previously reserved judgment as to how much technological enhancement of ordinary perception . . . , if any, is too much.” Even while recognizing the thermal imaging technology at issue to be “relatively crude,” the Court in Kyllo advocated adopting a rule that would “take account of more sophisticated systems that are already in use or in development.” At some point, the Court warned, technology might advance to the point where law enforcement could see through walls. Thus, even with the crude technology at issue in Kyllo, the potential for abuse was vast. In rejecting the government’s argument that only “intimate details” should be protected, the Court pointed out that the device might be able to reveal at what hour the lady of the house takes her nightly bath. Advanced forms of the technology—used without a warrant—would almost certainly “shrink the realm of guaranteed privacy.” While the Court was nominally protecting the “sanctity of the home,” the underlying rationale for Kyllo—as with the other surveillance cases—is the need to protect against police abuse. Thus the Court’s decision about whether a warrant is required turns on its structural concern about the potential for abuse.

C. The Ninth Circuit’s Error

The true distinction between Kyllo (warrant required) and Knotts (warrant not required), expressed subtly by the Court, eluded the Ninth Circuit. That court suggested that the thermal imaging technology in Kyllo triggered the Fourth Amendment because thermal imaging gathered information that otherwise would have been obtained only by “a search unequivocally within the meaning of the Fourth Amendment,”—i.e., a search of the home. However, that logic is flawed. The officers in Kyllo could have discovered the evidence by looking into the home from the outside with binoculars, and such surveillance would have been allowable without a warrant. The relevant distinction in Kyllo therefore must not be between evidence discovered indoors or outdoors but rather must be the Court’s discomfort with the use of a technology that showed vast abuse potential. With such superhero X-ray vision, walls were no longer a barrier against governmental surveillance. The Fourth Amendment’s Framers assumed certain physical “checks and balances” on governmental monitoring—e.g., that walls would not be transparent and that one officer would not be able to tail two different suspects in two different locations at one single moment. Where technological change has broken down these limitations, the Court has sought to restore them. This is the fundamental distinction between Knotts on the one hand and Kyllo, Katz,and Walter on the other. The Ninth Circuit ignored this important distinction and relied on Knotts,despite the government’s “limited use” of signals from the beeper.

In reaching its decision, the Ninth Circuit wrote off the Supreme Court’s concern about the potential for mass surveillance. According to Judge O’Scannlain, quoting the Seventh Circuit: “[s]hould [the] government someday decide to institute programs of mass surveillance of vehicular movements, it will be time enough to decide whether the Fourth Amendment should be interpreted to treat such surveillance as a search.” It is important to note, though, that there is nothing in the Ninth Circuit’s decision that would prevent “mass” surveillance. Imagine that law enforcement officials were engaged in mass surveillance of, for example, every person with a Latino surname who purchases fertilizer. One would need to adopt an extraordinarily impoverished view of the Fourth Amendment in order to consider this constitutionally permissible. But under the Ninth Circuit’s decision in Pineda-Moreno, law enforcement officials “conducted no search, and Pineda-Moreno can assert no Fourth Amendment violation,” no matter how unreasonable the “non-search” might have been.

II. The Unique Capabilities of GPS Technology

Once the source of the Court’s discomfort with new technologies is properly identified as a concern about law enforcement abuse, the problem with GPS surveillance technology becomes somewhat clearer. There is a vast technical valley between old technologies used by police officers, which merely assist in tailing suspects, and modern GPS surveillance technology, which automates tracking and surveillance. The unique capabilities of these automated systems, which turn over the surveillance function to machines, are constitutionally significant because they vastly increase the likelihood of abuse. In this Part, we describe how GPS surveillance technology works and demonstrate how its technical details create enormous potential for abuse.

A. GPS Surveillance Technology Operates Independently of Humans

Modern GPS surveillance technology is a satellite-based service consisting of three parts. First, a GPS receiver (the “tracking device”), which is generally minuscule and inexpensive, autonomously calculates latitude, longitude, altitude, direction, and speed by receiving and processing location information from the transmissions of at least four GPS satellites in nearby orbit. The average case location capabilities specified in the current (2008) GPS standard call for better than nine meters horizontal accuracy and better than fifteen meters vertical accuracy. The Nationwide Differential GPS (NDGPS) system enhancement enables an average location accuracy of one to three meters for compatible receivers and provides coverage over approximately ninety-two percent of the contiguous forty-eight states. Further improvement efforts underway seek to achieve within ten centimeters horizontal accuracy and twenty centimeters vertical accuracy.Second, a wireless transmitter attached to the tracking device sends the calculated location information to a specified remote destination. Finally, a law enforcement computer records the transmitted tracking data, stores it for an unlimited amount of time, and compares it with data collected from other targets. The first item comprises the “core” location-determining technology used in GPS surveillance; the second and third items are technologies to collect and process that location information for law enforcement use. Alternate methods of retrieving this information exist. Some GPS tracking devices can store the information internally. Officers can then manually retrieve the data, or they can do so remotely—by triggering short-duration (or “burst”) wireless transmissions—when they are within the device’s range.

Accordingly, electronic systems such as beeper devices used in the 1980s are simple tools when compared with modern GPS surveillance technology. As described by the Supreme Court in Knotts, “[a] beeper is a radio transmitter, usually battery operated, which emits periodic signals that can be picked up by a radio receiver.” After receiving the signal, the strength of which indicates whether the object to which the beeper is attached is approaching or moving away, police officers in the vicinity could use this information to respond accordingly. Beepers could neither determine the location themselves nor store that data. The beepers in Knotts are thus not at all analogous to GPS technology.

B. The Potential for Abuse

Two aspects of GPS surveillance technology make it prone to abuse. First, once the GPS tracking device is installed, it can operate autonomously over a prolonged period of time without human involvement, independently determining and remotely transmitting positional data twenty-four hours a day. Unlike the beepers in Knotts, police officers need not tail the GPS tracking device in order to determine location information. As Chief Judge Kozinski explains in his dissent from the denial of rehearing Pineda-Moreno en banc:

  Beepers could help police keep vehicles in view when following them, or find them when they lost sight of them, but they still required at least one officer—and usually many more—to follow the suspect. The modern devices used in Pineda-Moreno’s case can record the car’s movements without human intervention.  

The requirement that law enforcement officers actively maintain proximity to the surveillance device—a notable limitation of “beeper” and other similar transponder-based location systems—is simply not present when using GPS technology. In this way, GPS technology eliminates the constraint placed on police surveillance capabilities by the limited number of officers available at any given time to track the public’s movements. In the past, it was simply impossible for the police to assign an officer to track large groups of citizens around the clock. This new technology thus advances the government’s surveillance capabilities and “shrink[s] the realm of guaranteed privacy.” By far exceeding the human capacity for surveillance, these machines create the potential for surveillance of particular individuals, unpopular groups, and eventually the entire populace. This surveillance could remain entirely undetected.

Second, the electronic storage of gathered location data allows the data to be stored forever and considered at any time in the future alongside data collected from other citizens. In contrast to beeper data, which are lost forever unless an individual records and stores the information, GPS-associated computers can by themselves compare data gathered from different individuals and identify common patterns of behavior and gatherings of groups of people. As Chief Judge Kozinski commented:

  By tracking and recording the movements of millions of individuals the government can use computers to detect patterns and develop suspicions. It can also learn a great deal about us because where we go says much about who we are . . . . Were Jones, Aaronson and Rutherford at that protest outside the White House?  

GPS technology is capable of retaining information for an unlimited amount of time, making targets of tracking vulnerable to intrusive data analysis of where they went and who they saw for years after the fact.

C. Evidence of Use, Suggestions of Abuse

The precise scope of GPS surveillance is unknown; there are no nationwide statistics available on the frequency of GPS surveillance, and most police departments resist disclosing how often they use it. However, the Federal Law Enforcement Training Center has issued a special bulletin advising officers in the use of GPS technology, and some local jurisdictions have willingly reported the scope of their use. For example, one police department in Fairfax, Virginia reported using GPS surveillance sixty-one times in 2005 alone. The ACLU and its affiliates recently filed 379 public records requests in thirty-one states to determine the scope of GPS surveillance more precisely. As we await responses to those requests, accounts of GPS surveillance are necessarily anecdotal. The president of the National Association of Criminal Defense Lawyers, for instance, reports that GPS surveillance has been used “in cases from New York City to small towns—whoever can afford to get the equipment and plant it on a car.”

In one recent incident, a twenty-year-old college student from Santa Clara, California, Yasir Afifi, discovered a GPS surveillance device affixed to his car. Afifi is an American citizen whose father, also an American citizen, was president of a Muslim community association in the United States before moving to Egypt in 2003. Forty-eight hours after Afifi removed the device and asked for help online to identify it, he received a visit from several FBI agents who demanded the return of the device. Afifi was then questioned about an online blog maintained by his close friend. To date, he has not been charged with a crime. The FBI, after reclaiming the tracking device, has provided no further details.

The anecdotal evidence presented here—the Fairfax data, the FBI bulletin, the Afifi case, and so on—fall well short of the “mass, suspicionless surveillance” that the Solicitor General says might trigger a warrant requirement. Yet it is worth reflecting for a moment on what circumstances might trigger such “mass, suspicionless surveillance”—e.g., a terrorist attack by enemies (either foreign or domestic) whose ethnicity, religious affiliation, political persuasion, or other characteristics catalyze fear of or animus toward a particular minority group. It seems strange to say that under those circumstances, courts would shift from the no-warrant default rule to a heightened standard of Fourth Amendment protection. After all, civil liberties in times of emergency are subject to a one-way ratchet, and the direction is down. The rules we set now, in “normal” times, ten years after the last attack on U.S. soil, serve as a ceiling, not a floor. The Solicitor General’s claim that the warrant question “can await resolution” until we see an uptick in use of GPS surveillance ignores the political economy of emergency.

III. GPS Surveillance, Dignity Interests, and Core Constitutional Rights

So far, the analysis in this Essay has not yet tackled the Supreme Court’s “expectation of privacy” standard, which complicates—but ultimately strengthens—our argument. As then-Justice Rehnquist recognized in Knotts, “th[e] Court uniformly has held that the application of the Fourth Amendment depends on whether the person invoking its protection can claim a justifiable, a reasonable, or a legitimate expectation of privacy that has been invaded by government action.” In Pineda-Moreno, the Ninth Circuit relied on Knotts to hold that the government can use GPS surveillance technology without warrants because individuals have no reasonable expectation of privacy in their movements through public space. But individuals do have a “reasonable expectation” that they are not being watched (at least not constantly), and that expectation is threatened by GPS surveillance, regardless of whether the expectation attaches to any particular fact on its own.

Moreover, and more importantly, a robust Fourth Amendment cannot depend on whether individuals expect that particular facts will be kept private. If that were the case, then in a scenario in which the government ignored privacy rights on a vast scale—as in George Orwell’s Nineteen Eighty-Four, Terry Gilliam’s 1985 movie Brazil, or the contemporary children’s book The Hunger Games—there would be no expectation of privacy at all. The Ninth Circuit’s interpretation of the “expectation of privacy” criterion creates the paradoxical situation in which law enforcement overreach is legitimized once it becomes routinized. Surely, the Fourth Amendment is robust enough that it would not lose its force if members of the public came to think that “Big Brother” behavior on the part of police officers was par for the course.

To be tenable, the “expectation of privacy” requirement must protect something more than our predictions whether a particular fact or act will lie outside the state’s line of sight. The D.C. Circuit’s analysis in Maynard seemed to grasp this need.The circuit court concluded that prolonged GPS surveillance allows the government to develop an overall picture of people’s lives that goes far beyond what individuals expect others to know about their actions. Our E-ZPass account records and airline reservations might reveal our comings and goings in broad brushstrokes, but GPS surveillance allows the government to see our microlevel movements: what house of worship we attend, and how often; whether we see a psychiatrist; with whom we spend the night; where we eat; where we exercise; and whether we attend a particular political organization’s meetings. That this information might be discoverable through credit card records or other sources is no answer: when news broke that the FBI had accessed credit card records without a warrant, the Justice Department’s Inspector General called the actions “serious misconduct.” By contrast, the Justice Department does not apologize for warrantless GPS surveillance; rather, it unabashedly defends the practice.

The following sections elaborate two interpretations of “expectation of privacy”: one in which the expectation attaches to specific facts and acts and is dependent on the context of actions and behavior, and another in which the expectation protects a less clearly delineated sphere of personal and communal life. We contend that both understandings support Fourth Amendment protection in the GPS context, though only the latter addresses the argument, mentioned above, that a prediction-based privacy right will paradoxically grow weaker as government intrusions into the private sphere grow more severe.

A. Expectation Depends on Context

Taking seriously the Supreme Court’s mandate that we must not allow new technology to “shrink the private realm” requires us to examine the impact that the means of surveillance, the nature of the technology at issue, and its potential for abuse will have on our privacy expectations. Where technology changes what is visible and knowable about us, we cannot afford to revive the rejected Fourth Amendment doctrine that attempted to draw a strict line between public and private space based on notions of physical trespass.

As the D.C. Circuit concluded, GPS surveillance invades a reasonable expectation of privacy because prolonged surveillance from the sky allows the government to develop an overall picture of people’s lives that goes far beyond what individuals expect others to know about their public actions. Specifically, it is the prolonged nature of the surveillance that creates the problem. Prolonged use of GPS surveillance technology allows the collection of a more detailed view of a person’s life and activities than that gained by short bursts of tracking, both because the duration of the tracking allows the collection of more information and because GPS technology collects an unprecedented amount of detail on its target’s movements. This approach to evaluating whether an invasion of privacy has occurred, described by the D.C. Circuit as recognizing that “the whole is something different than the sum of its parts,” is not novel. Instead, it is a straightforward application of the rule that whether a law enforcement search is “reasonable” is a fact-specific inquiry that must be determined through review of “the totality of the circumstances.” Indeed, this type of analysis—rather than reliance on public versus private space—is required by Katz, where the Court held that “what [a person] seeks to preserve as private, even in an area accessible to the public, may be constitutionally protected.”

As Helen Nissenbaum points out, where behavior occurs is not always determinative of the private nature of that behavior; instead, “norms of appropriateness dictate what information about persons is appropriate, or fitting, to reveal in a particular context.” She argues:

  [W]hether a particular action is determined a violation of privacy is a function of several variables, including the nature of the situation, or context; the nature of the information in relation to that context; the roles of agents receiving information; their relationships to information subjects; on what terms the information is shared by the subject; and the terms of further dissemination.  

The Supreme Court has followed this logical approach to determining privacy expectations in another context. For example, in Ferguson v. City of Charleston, the Court recognized that there is a difference between handing over one’s bodily fluids for drug testing in a medical context and handing over one’s bodily fluids outside a medical context. Because “[t]he reasonable expectation of privacy enjoyed by the typical patient undergoing diagnostic tests in a hospital is that the results of those tests will not be shared with nonmedical personnel without her consent,” the plaintiffs in that case had an expectation of privacy in the results of drug tests of fluids they shared with medical personnel. The expectation of privacy differs based on whowas given the fluids and in what context.

Similarly, context determines whether we expect privacy while driving on public highways—or in any public setting. As Nissenbaum argues, “[t]he notion that when individuals venture out in public . . . ‘anything goes,’ is pure fiction. . . . [E]ven in the most public of places, it is not out of order for people to respond in word or thought, ‘none of your business,’ to a stranger asking their names.” Michael Froomkin points out that “at least in large cities, one enjoys the illusion, and to a large extent the reality, of being able to move about with anonymity.” In fact, the conception of privacy as a form of total secrecy is ill-suited to the digital information age: “[t]he people we call, the papers we discard, and our financial records are commonly understood as private matters even though third-parties may have access to (or even possess) that information.” Ultimately, “clinging to the notion of privacy as total secrecy would mean the practical extinction of privacy in today’s world.”

Additionally, the public’s behavior toward encroaching forms of surveillance is relevant to whether courts can infer that the public believes certain actions are private. On this count, the American public has clearly rejected the notion that the government should be able to follow us without our consent. Although many Americans are comfortable with using a GPS service to determine their own personal location when that service operates subject to their consent and control, Americans are uncomfortable with GPS surveillance technology when there is even a slight loss of user control. For example, despite a strong push by companies encouraging Americans to adopt “geosocial” software that would allow users to broadcast their locations to selected friends using GPS in their phones, only four percent of online adult Americans use these services. For those skeptical whether there can be any plausible privacy expectation for these public actions, as Chief Judge Kozinski noted, “[y]ou can preserve your anonymity from prying eyes, even in public, by traveling at night, through heavy traffic, in crowds, by using a circuitous route, disguising your appearance, passing in and out of buildings and being careful not to be followed.” As the Maynard court observed, we have not become a society that expects this monitoring of our daily activities, and there is no sign that we would accept that type of oversight.

Indeed, even the federal government recognizes that members of the American public do not expect to disclose data about their movements from place to place throughout the day. To recruit volunteers whose vehicles would be equipped with GPS devices for a federally funded study to assess a new mileage-based tax, study organizers felt it necessary to assure volunteers that “[n]o detailed route information regarding your driving will be stored or collected” and that information about mileage would be maintained in “highly secure locations” in a separate database on a separate server from their personal information. The organizers’ assurances indicate their recognition of a reasonable expectation of privacy in data about public movements.

B. Privacy as Self-Definition and Dignity

When our activities and our patterns of behavior are exposed to view, our sphere of self shrinks accordingly. The expectation that these “private” matters will be known to others has the potential to change our behavior and ultimately who we are.These expected intrusions inflict upon us a different identity; they force a schism between true identity and expressed identity. In constitutional parlance, they chill the exercise of constitutionally protected activity—speech, thoughts, and behaviors—especially those that involve criticisms of the existing government or that are seen as odious by government officials. The “expectation of privacy” standard has always been used to help us identify the aspects of life that are vital to our sense of well-being, aspects that have been referred to in the past as interests in privacy and now are sometimes talked about as aspects of “dignity” or interests in self-definition. Expectations of privacy also play an essential role in civic and democratic life. As the Court has recognized, there is a “vital relationship between freedom to associate and privacy in one’s associations. . . . Inviolability of privacy in group association may in many circumstances be indispensable to preservation of freedom of association, particularly where a group espouses dissident beliefs.” With such deep personal values at stake, the “expectation of privacy” ought to be conceived of as what the individual believes to be crucial to his or her sense of self.

One might naturally ask why a warrant requirement changes the landscape so dramatically: after all, we would still never know for sure whether we were the subject of surveillance by the government. And yet the requirement that law enforcement officials justify their surveillance decisions to judges ensures that the “machines” are watching only with good reason, not based on a whim, prejudice, or desire to discover disliked behavior. As such, it prevents the schism of self that threatens our dignitary interests.

Professor Kerr has objected that a rule requiring judges to sign off on GPS surveillance will lead to judicial confusion and inconsistency. But this concern is a red herring. Simply requiring law enforcement officials to ask for a warrant imposes a limit on the expansion rate of the scope of surveillance. There may indeed be tough decisions for courts to make about whether limited use of GPS surveillance (e.g., tracking a suspect for a single day) triggers the Fourth Amendment warrant requirement. But this is why we have judges, and they will use all the criteria they apply to other surveillance situations—including the practical considerations about the ability to obtain a warrant—here. Even if judges grant warrants for GPS surveillance liberally, the requirement that law enforcement authorities justify each use of GPS surveillance prevents them from multiplying this monitoring by millions.

Conclusion

When used properly, advanced surveillance technologies significantly enhance the ability of law enforcement to maintain order and public safety. However, the Ninth Circuit’s strained, mechanical application of Knotts and the proposed bright-line rule between behavior indoors and behavior outdoors leaves fundamental interests protected by the Fourth Amendment unguarded. Without a warrant requirement to guide its use and constrain its growth, the potential for abuseof GPS surveillance technology is vast, and its use will significantly “shrink the realm of guaranteed personal privacy.” Moreover, it will upset the system of checks and balances—physical as well as legal—that the Framers expected would apply to future generations. The Jones case affords the Supreme Court an opportunity to step in and clarify that, as with any new technologies that allow machines to do the watching, GPS surveillance technology can only be used for prolonged, automated surveillance on the authority of a warrant. Such clarification may go a long way toward resolving the confusion that the Court’s prior Fourth Amendment case law has wrought.

The authors are Fellows of the Information Society Project at Yale Law School (ISP), an intellectual center addressing the implications of new information technologies for law and society. Priscilla J. Smith is a Senior Fellow of the ISP, focusing on reproductive rights, privacy law, information policy, and new technologies. Smith litigated cases concerning constitutional rights to liberty, privacy, and freedom of speech for thirteen years at the Center for Reproductive Rights. She holds a J.D. from Yale Law School. Nabiha Syed is currently the First Amendment Fellow at the New York Times. She holds a J.D. from Yale Law School and is the author of Replicating Dreams (2008). David Thaw is a (Postdoctoral) Research Associate in the Department of Computer Science at the University of Maryland and practices information security and privacy law in Washington, D.C. Thaw has published multiple articles and book chapters based on his research in information security, privacy, and spyware. He holds a Ph.D. (Information Management and Systems), a J.D., and an M.A. (Political Science) from the University of California, Berkeley. Albert Wong is a Ph.D. candidate in Cell Biology at Yale University. Wong has published multiple peer-reviewed articles in engineering and biology and is supported by a National Institutes of Health National Research Service Award. He holds an S.M. (Health Sciences and Technology) from the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. The authors would like to thank Jack Balkin, Laura DeNardis, and the other fellows of the ISP for providing us with a rich forum in which to engage on these issues and for their many important insights. They also thank the editors of The Yale Law Journal Online for their useful suggestions, which have greatly improved this Essay.

Preferred citation: Priscilla J. Smith, Nabiha Syed, David Thaw & Albert Wong, When Machines Are Watching: How Warrantless Use of GPS Surveillance Technology Violates the Fourth Amendment Right Against Unreasonable Searches, 121 Yale L.J. Online 177 (2011), http://yalelawjournal.org/forum/when-machines-are-watching-how-warrantless-use-of-gps-surveillance-technology-violates-the-fourth-amendment-right-against-unreasonable-searches.